The '''Turing test''' is a proposal for a test of a machine's capability to perform human-like conversation. Described by
Nextel ringtones Alan Turing in the 1950 paper "
Abbey Diaz Computing machinery and intelligence", it proceeds as follows: a human judge engages in a natural language conversation with two other parties, one a human and the other a machine; if the judge cannot reliably tell which is which, then the machine is said to pass the test. It is assumed that both the human and the machine try to appear human. In order to keep the test setting simple and universal (to explicitly test the linguistic capability of some machine), the conversation is usually limited to a text-only channel.
HistoryThe test was inspired by a
Free ringtones party game known as the "Imitation Game", in which a man and a woman go into separate rooms, and guests try to tell them apart by writing a series of questions and reading the typewritten answers sent back. In this game, both the man and the woman aim to convince the guests that they are the woman.
Turing originally proposed the test in order to replace the emotionally charged and for him meaningless question "Can machines think?" with a more well-defined one.
One interesting part of his proposed test was that the answers in conversation would have to be delivered at controlled intervals and rates. He believed this necessary to prevent the observer drawing a conclusion based on the fact the computer potentially would answer so much ''faster'' than the human operator, especially on mathematical questions.
Objections and repliesTuring himself suggested several objections which could be made to the test. Below are some of the objections and replies from the article in which Turing first proposed the test.
#''Theological Objection'': This states that thinking is a function of man's
Majo Mills immortal
Nextel ringtones soul and therefore a machine could not think. Turing replies by saying that he sees no reason why it would not be possible for God to grant a computer a soul if he so wished.
#''Mathematical Objections'': This objection uses mathematical theorems, such as
Abbey Diaz Gödel's incompleteness theorem, to show that there are limits to what questions a computer system based on
Mosquito ringtone logic can answer. Turing suggests that humans are too often wrong themselves and pleased at the fallibility of a machine.
#''Argument From Consciousness'': This argument, suggested by Professor Jefferson Lister states, "not until a machine can write a sonnet or compose a concerto because of thoughts and emotions felt, and not by the chance fall of symbols, could we agree that machine equals brain". Turing replies by saying that we have no way of knowing that any individual other than ourselves experiences emotions, and that therefore we should accept the test.
#''Lady Lovelace Objection'': One of the most famous objections, it states that computers are incapable of originality. Turing replies that computers could still surprise humans, in particular where the consequences of different facts are not immediately recognizable.
#''Informality of Behaviour'': This argument states that any system governed by laws will be predictable and therefore not truly intelligent. Turing replies by stating that this is confusing laws of behaviour with general rules of conduct.
#''Extra-sensory perception'': Turing seems to suggest that there is evidence for
Sabrina Martins extra-sensory perception. However he feels that conditions could be created in which this would not affect the test and so may be disregarded.
Discussion of relevanceIt has been argued that the Turing test can not serve as a valid definition of machine
Nextel ringtones intelligence (trait)/intelligence or "machine thinking" for at least three reasons:
# A machine passing the Turing test may be able to ''simulate human conversational behavior'', but this may be much weaker than true intelligence. The machine might just follow some cleverly devised rules. (A common rebuttal in the AI community has been to ask: how do we know humans don't just follow some cleverly devised rules?) Two famous examples of this line of argument against the Turing test are
Abbey Diaz John Searle's
Cingular Ringtones Chinese room argument and
and besmirch Ned Block's
borderline separatist Blockhead argument.
# A machine may very well be intelligent without being able to chat like a human.
# Many humans that we'd probably want to consider intelligent might fail this test (e.g. the young or the illiterate). (On the other hand, the intelligence of fellow humans is almost always tested exclusively based on their utterances.)
Another potential problem, related to the first objection above, is that even if the Turing test is a good operational definition of intelligence, it may not indicate that the machine has
called yip consciousness, or that it has
suppress pending intentionality. Perhaps intelligence and consciousness, for example, are such that neither one necessarily implies the other. In that case, the Turing test might fail to capture one of the key differences between intelligent machines and intelligent people. Of course, machines passing the test would most likely vehemently disagree.
Predictions and tests Turing predicted that machines would eventually be able to pass the test. In fact, he estimated that by the year 2000, machines with 109
effort are bit/bits (about 119MB) of memory would be able to fool 30% of human judges during a 5-minute test. He also predicted that people would then no longer consider the phrase "thinking machine" contradictory. He further predicted that
study provides machine learning would be an important part of building powerful machines, a claim which is considered to be plausible by contemporary researchers in
shultz who Artificial intelligence.
quarter some As of 2004, no computer has passed the Turing test as such. Simple conversational programs such as
social monsters ELIZA have fooled people into believing they are talking to another human being, such as in an informal experiment termed
hey at AOLiza. However, such "successes" are not the same as a Turing Test. Most obviously, the human party in the conversation has no reason to suspect they are talking to anything other than a human, whereas in a real Turing test the questioner is actively trying to determine the nature of the entity they are chatting with. Documented cases are usually in environments such as
virtues of Internet Relay Chat where conversation is sometimes stilted and meaningless, and in which no understanding of a conversation is necessary, are common. Additionally, many internet relay chat participants use English as a second or third language, thus making it even more likely that they would assume that an unintelligent comment by the conversational program is simply something they have misunderstood, and are also
probably unfamiliar with the technology of "chat bots" and don't recognize the very non-human errors they make. See
nuggets january ELIZA effect.
The
iii originally Loebner prize is an annual competition to determine the best Turing test competitors. Although they award an annual prize for the computer system that, in the judges' opinions, demonstrates the "most human" conversational behaviour (with
dead genuity A.L.I.C.E. being a recent winner multiple times), they have an additional prize for a system that in their opinion passes a Turing test. This second prize has not yet been awarded.
There is an ongoing $10,000 bet at the
dan goldie Long Now/Long Bets Foundation between
blaspheming scholars Mitch Kapor and
stayed so Ray Kurzweil about the question whether a computer will pass a Turing Test by the year
record revenues 2029. The bet specifies the Turing Test in some detail.
TerminologyIn Turing's paper, the term "Imitation Game" is used for his proposed test as well as the party game for men and women. The name "Turing test" may have been invented, and was certainly publicized, by
and resold Arthur C. Clarke in the
bought in 1968 science fiction/science-fiction novel 2001: A Space Odyssey.
References* "Computing machinery and intelligence" by Alan Turing, ''Mind'', vol. LIX, no. 236, October 1950, pp. 433-460. Online versions: http://cogprints.soton.ac.uk/documents/disk0/00/00/04/99/],
* ''The Emperor's New Mind'' by Roger Penrose, a book on these subjects
See also* Artificial intelligence
* Captcha, Chatterbot
* Chinese Room
* Blockhead
* Loebner prize
* Mark V Shaney (computer program)
* Reverse Turing test
External links* http://plato.stanford.edu entry on http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/turing-test, by G. Oppy and http://www.csse.monash.edu.au/~dld.
* http://cogsci.ucsd.edu/~asaygin/tt/ttest.html lists recent articles, links, and other info on the test.
* http://crl.ucsd.edu/~saygin/papers/MMTT.pdf reviews a half-century of work on the Turing Test, from the vantage point of 2000.
* http://www.longbets.org/1, including detailed justifications of their respective positions.
* http://www.cogs.susx.ac.uk/users/blayw/tt.html by Blay Witby
* http://www.twinkiesproject.com/turing.html at proving the non-intelligence of a Twinkie
* New York Times essays on machine intelligence http://www.rci.rutgers.edu/~cfs/472_html/Intro/NYT_Intro/History/MachineIntelligence2.html and http://www.rci.rutgers.edu/~cfs/472_html/Intro/NYT_Intro/History/MachineIntelligence2.html
ca:Test de Turing
cs:Turingův test
de:Turing-Test
es:Prueba de Turing
fr:Test de Turing
nl:Turing-test
ja:チューリング・テスト
pl:Test Turinga
ru:Тест Тьюринга
uk:Тест Тьюрінга
zh:图灵试验
Tag: Artificial intelligence
Tag: Alan Turing